CTHEORY:
THEORY, TECHNOLOGY AND CULTURE VOL 30, NOS 1-2 |
The brain thinks, not man. Man
is just a cerebral crystallization.
What can a philosopher say about phantom limb syndrome? More specifically, what can a materialist philosopher say about phantom limb syndrome? At first glance, a phenomenon by which our 'corporeal imagination' -- what La Mettrie in the eighteenth century called the "magic lantern" working within the brain, projecting images created by our memory and intellect [3] -- induces us to feel pains in a missing limb might seem like profound evidence that naive, scientistic views of consciousness are false or at least useless. How could science with its measurements ever grasp the irreducibly subjective construction which my body is? Notice that in any case, regardless of our answer to such a question, a somato-psychic phenomenon like phantom limb syndrome raises significant issues regarding good old-fashioned notions such as the self, and slightly less old-fashioned notions such as the tandem 'self and brain'. Namely, if the self has already been deflated -- since Hume and Nietzsche in their respective traditions, and in recent times since Dennett -- what about the brain? Our suspicions regarding nefarious neurophilosophers and other ~herauts~
of scientism should be allayed, or at least mollified, by the realization
that present-day neuroscience and philosophy of The box is made by placing a vertical mirror inside a cardboard box
with the roof of the box removed. The front of the box has two holes
in it, through which the patient inserts his good arm and his phantom
arm. The patient is then asked to view the reflection of his normal
hand in the mirror, thus creating the Now, in what follows my aim is less to stake out a position on phantom
limbs (real? imagined? material? neuronal? phenomenal?) than to show
that philosophical reflection on brains, even when it seeks to rebut
the dogmatic anti-naturalism found in most corners of phenomenology,
does not have to be naively, crudely reductionistic or scientistic --
in other words, to show that one can be a materialist My argument runs as follows: 1. What do phantom limbs seem to imply? The first-person perspective. 2. But a materialist response to this first-person challenge is possible. Further, it has to be an embodied materialist response. 3. However, in order to not reinvest the brain with the mysterious
character that the self has lost, this must also be an embedded vision
of the brain, not just in the body but in the network of symbolic relations.
One can describe this as the 'social brain', and emphasize the coeval,
co-originary relation Phantom limbs and anosognosias -- cases of abnormal impressions of
the presence or absence of parts of our body[8] -- seem like handy illustrations
of an irreducible, first-person dimension of Although the materialist might agree with the (reformed) phenomenologist to reject dualism and accept that we are not in our bodies like a sailor in a ship, she might not want to go and declare, as Merleau-Ponty does, that "the mind does not use the body, but fulfills itself through it while at the same time transferring the body outside of physical space."[11] This way of talking goes back to the Husserlian distinction between Korper, 'body' in the sense of one body among others in a vast mechanistic universe of bodies, and Leib, 'flesh' in the sense of a subjectivity which is the locus of experience. Now, granted, in cognitivist terms one would want to say that a representation is always my representation, it is not 'transferable' like a neutral piece of information, since the way an object appears to me is always a function of my needs and interests. What my senses tell me at any given time relies on my interests as an agent and is determined by them, as described by Andy Clark, who appeals to the combined research traditions of the psychology of perception, new robotics, and Artificial Life. But the phenomenologist will take off from there and build a full-blown defense of intentionality, now recast as 'motor intentionality' (as currently discussed by neuroscientists such as Alain Berthoz and Marc Jeannerod and philosophers such as Sean Kelly), a notion which goes back to Husserl's claim in _Ideas II_ that the way the body relates to the external world is crucially through "kinestheses": all external motions which we perceive are first of all related to kinesthetic sensations, out of which we constitute a sense of space. On this view, our body thus already displays 'originary intentionality' in how it relates to the world. This is part of what I mean by the appeal to the first-person dimension.
In contrast, for someone like Dennett, phantom limbs and agnosias are,
at least as much as they are instances of self-reference, instances
of self-deception: we don't have a transparent relation to ourselves.
"You are not authoritative about what is happening in you, but
only about what seems to be happening in you,"[12] or, as Andy
Clark puts it, "the conscious self is but the tip of the 'I' berg."[13]
Phantom limb phenomena merely bring to light a much wider sense in which
we live in 'intended' rather than For your entire life, you've been walking around assuming that your
'self' is anchored to a single body that remains stable and permanent
at least until death... yet these results suggest the exact opposite
-- that your body image... is an entirely transitory construct that
can be profoundly altered with just a Our self -- and its neural correlates -- is a construct, at most a
"narrative center,"[17] and by that token, it's a fiction
(as first seen by Hume, and also Montaigne). I am a character in a story
my As I said initially, phantom limbs and related phenomena seem like ideal cases for the phenomenologist (whether slightly favourable to a naturalistic viewpoint or not), of a bodily state in which the viewpoint of the subject is an irreducible part of the state, such that if it were factored out, that 'state' would no longer make any sense, indeed would no longer exist. 2. The 'trivially true' materialist response here would be to say: these
are cases of 'remapping' the inner 'model' of the body we have, known
as the cortical map[22] or the Penfield map (after the Canadian (a) To lay out the third-person, externalist perspective, it's always helpful to remember that there is no homunculus: The cardinal background principle [for the neurophilosopher] is that
there are no homunculi. There is no little person in the brain who 'sees'
an inner television screen, 'hears' an inner voice, 'reads' the topographic
maps, weighs reasons, decides actions, and so forth. There are just
neurons and their And there are no qualia either. As Dennett has memorably written,
believers in qualia are tied to a picture of the mind as a 'Cartesian
theatre', in which mental entities are on display before the mind's Thomas Nagel's famous appeal to subjective experience in "What
is it like to be a bat?"[26] is an elegant revival or recycling
of the phenomenological vulgate from the Continent, a 'minimal credo'
one Human and other subjects can have functionally or computationally different states that nonetheless home on the same objective state of affairs, either external or internal. But there are no intrinsically subjective or perspectival facts that are either the special objects of self-regarding attitudes or facts of 'what it is like'. There are only states of subjects that both function in a particularly intimate way within those subjects and have the subjects themselves and their other states as inevitable referents. And that is all there is to 'subjectivity'.[27] (b) More interestingly, and moving towards 'embodiment', Paul Churchland
has pointed out that we can claim to have a first-person, privileged
relation to all sorts of physical things, including our muscles, The existence of a proprietary, first-person epistemological access to some phenomenon does not mean that the accessed phenomenon is nonphysical in nature. It means only that someone possesses an information-carrying causal connection to that phenomenon, a connection that others lack.[31] The materialist can accept that we have "a route of epistemological
access" to our own body, which others lack (this is not Merleau-Ponty
but the Australian identity theorist David Armstrong!), and thereby
also to our mind.[32] But it must be explained: "there remains
a genuine obligation on the materialist's part to give some account
of the subjectivity or perspectivalness or point-of-view-ness of the
mental"; "the materialist owes the world an explanation of
what it is about a mental/neural state that makes its proprietor think
of it as subjective."[33] In other words, instead of denying the
existence of What proprioception -- among other biological phenomena -- tells us
is that even if we were restricting ourselves to 'biological talk',
we would end up with some account of our subjective relation to the Indeed, since the embodied materialist standpoint is not merely a
physicalism but can appeal to biological information, it offers plenty
of ways to understand individuality, selfhood or agency, from 3. The trick is to not go all the way with embodiment, so as not to end
up in what Deleuze, speaking of Merleau-Ponty, called the "mysticism
of the flesh."[40] After all, is there anything metaphysically
unique about flesh, skin or the brain which makes them do what they
do? My last point, then, is to not get too comfortable with embodiment
either, since the brain is necessarily located within the social and Namely, if we demystify or deflate some concepts of self and subjectivity by relating such concepts to the reality of the brain -- the processes of which are dynamic, distributed, non-centred, dissipative, and include 'remapping' -- we shouldn't then turn the brain itself into a mysterious substance which explains everything, some sort of 'Wonder Tissue'; a corrective is needed. If mind and body belong together, as do body and brain, so do brain and world. Call this the "co-evolutionary" perspective (with Terrence
Deacon) and emphasize 'Baldwinian evolution', i.e., the cluster of linguistic
and cultural layers in evolution which do not fall under Darwinian Think of it in terms of plasticity: the possibility, as described
in Ramachandran's mirror box experiment, of reviving volitional control
and somatic sensations in a phantom arm by simply using a mirror, even
when no sensation had been experienced by the subject for the previous
ten years, "implies a surprising degree of plasticity in the adult
brain."[45] And this plasticity implies in turn a surprising In any case, my point is not to take a position in the current debates on the status and importance of neural plasticity,[49] but rather to emphasize the 'scaffolding' dimension, which implies -- at the risk of sounding a bit like a practitioner of 'Theory' -- that the 'paradigm' of the phantom limb might not be not so far removed from that of the prosthesis. Given the degree of openness of the central nervous system, and on
the 'personal' level, our ability to identify with non-biological extensions
of our body, the 'artificialist' perspective, in which body and prosthesis,
indeed, body and tool, merge, is not so far off. Just as the 'fictional
self' is the outcome of the deflation of the ontological unity of self,
the social, evolving, 'cultured'[50] brain deflates the ontological
uniqueness and isolation of the brain. The tool... has entirely changed. We no longer need tools in order to transform nature... or to establish a relation with the historical world..., we only need language. Language is the tool. Better yet, the brain is the tool, inasmuch as it is common.[52] The brain is "common" inasmuch as it is constituted by and
inseparable from the network of relations to which we belong. If phantom
limb syndrome was the point of entry here by which the brain opens onto
the world of fiction, revealing our sense of self, including its 'embodied'
dimension, to be a "transitory internal construct," in Ramachandran's
terms, then the prosthesis (akin in this respect to certain appropriations
of the figure of the cyborg) is the point at which the brain escapes
any solipsism, whether of the post-Cartesian, brain-in-a-vat sort, or
the more omnipotent, brain-as-self sort. If one thinks of the recent
examples of theperformers Stelarc and Orlan (regardless of their different The common brain or social brain generates the fictional self, but really, the fellow-traveler of such a self should be termed the de-ontologized brain. Now, one can ask in response if a de-ontologized brain can "think ontologically,"[54] and the initial response seems to be No: if an ontology amounts to a definition or catalogue of what there is, as opposed to what there isn't (tables, chairs, bodies and maybe mathematical entities, but not centaurs or smiles of Cheshire cats), then brains as entities 'plugged in' to the network of artificialist, technological production shouldn't think ontologically at all. However, if one understands ontology in a sense closer to the "production of subjectivity," namely, as "constitutive ontology," in Negri's terms, then there is no tension between a plastic, social, cultured brain-in-a-network and the constant production and reproduction of being, through the desires and actions of concrete agents.[55] If what there is, is constituted, the brain's positing and desiring are no more real than the fictional, "forensick" masks of the self, but they are also no less real than the social, ethical and political forms into which they crystallize. Acknowledgments: A shorter version of this paper was presented at the conference on 'Phantom Limb Phenomena. Neuroscientific, Aesthetic, Philosophical Perspectives', Goldsmiths College, University of London, January 14-16, 2005. Many thanks to John Symons (UT El Paso) for steering me in the right direction with some of this material. Notes: [1] Gilles Deleuze & Felix Guattari, _Qu'est-ce que la philosophie?_, Paris: Minuit, 1991, pp. 197-198. [2] Bernard Mandeville, _A Treatise of the hypochondriack and hysterick diseases_, 2nd corrected edition, London: Tonson, 1730; reprint, Delmar, N.Y., Scholars' Reprints, 1976, p. 137. [3] Julien Offray de La Mettrie, _L'Homme-Machine_ (1748), in Aram Vartanian, _La Mettrie's "L'Homme-Machine." A Study in the Origins of An Idea_, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1960, p. 165. La Mettrie adds that the soul as a whole can be reduced to the workings of the imagination. [4] See Todd E. Feinberg & David M. Roane, "Anosognosia, completion and confabulation: the neutral-personal dichotomy," _Neurocase_ 3 (1997) and William Hirstein, _Brain Fiction. Self-Deception and the riddle of confabulation_, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2005 (an important work which addresses several of the concerns in the present essay). [5] V.S. Ramachandran & L. Levi et al., "Illusions of body image," in Rodolfo Llinás & Patricia S. Churchland, eds., _The Mind-Brain continuum: sensory processes_, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1996; V.S. Ramachandran & William Hirstein, "The Perception of phantom limbs" (D.O. Hebb lecture), _Brain 121_ (1998). [6] Ramachandran & Hirstein, "The Perception of phantom limbs," p. 1620. [7] Daniel Dennett, "The Myth of double transduction," _Toward a science of consciousness II, The Second Tucson discussions and debates_, eds. S. Hameroff, A.W. Kaszniak & A.C. Scott, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1998, p. 97. [8] See Antonio Damasio, _Descartes' Error. Emotion and reason in the human brain_, New York: Putnam, 1994, pp. 62-66. [9] Feinberg & Roane, "Anosognosia, completion and confabulation: the neutral-personal dichotomy." [10] As quoted in Ramachandran & Hirstein, "The Perception of phantom limbs," p. 1604. [11] Maurice Merleau-Ponty, _The Structure of behavior_, trans. A.L. Fisher, Boston: Beacon Press, 1963, pp. 208-209 (trans. modified). [12] Daniel Dennett, _Consciousness Explained_, Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1990, p. 96. [13] Andy Clark, _Natural-Born Cyborgs. Minds, technologies and the future of human intelligence_, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002, p. 100. [14] Borrowing this formulation from Chris Frith (discussion, London, 2005). [15] V.S. Ramachandran & Sandra Blakeslee, _Phantoms in the brain_, New York: W. Morrow, 1998, p. 62. [16] Ibid.; the body image is a "transitory internal construct" (Ramachandran & Hirstein, "The Perception of phantom limbs," p. 1623). [17] Dennett, _Consciousness Explained_, ch. 13, esp. pp. 426-427; "The Self as center of narrative gravity," in F.J. Kessel, P. Cole & D.L. Johnson, eds., _Self and consciousness: multiple perspectives_, Hillsdale, NJ: L. Erlbaum, 1992; Antonio Damasio, _The Feeling of what happens_, New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1999, ch. 7. [18] Drew McDermott, "Little 'me'" (commentary on Daniel Dennett & Marcel Kinsbourne, "Time and the observer"), _Brain and Behavioral Sciences_ 15:2 (1992), p. 217. [19] N. Katherine Hayles, "Flesh and Metal: Reconfiguring the Mindbody in Virtual Environments," _Configurations_ 10 (2002), p. 319. [20] Daniel Dennett, _Elbow Room. The varieties of
free will worth wanting_, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1984, p. 40,
n. 23, referring to Michael S. Gazzaniga & Joseph E. Ledoux, _The
Integrated Mind_, New York: Plenum, 1978. See also, inter alia, Gazzaniga,
"The Neuronal Platonist" (interview by Shaun Gallagher), _Journal
of [21] See Kurt Goldstein, T_he Organism: a holistic approach to biology derived from pathological data in man_, New York: Zone Books / MIT Press, 1995 (originally published 1934). In modern neuroscience Goldstein's role as a predecessor of more recent split-brain studies has been seen by Norman Geschwind, "Disconnexion syndromes in animals and man," _Brain_ 88 (1965). [22] See Nicholas Humphrey, _A History of the mind_, New York: Simon & Schuster, 1992, pp. 171-176, here, p. 172. [23] For more on the 'embodiment' paradigm in cognitive science, see Francisco Varela, Evan Thompson & Eleanor Rosch, _The Embodied Mind_, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1991. [24] Patricia S. Churchland, _Neurophilosophy: towards a unified science of the mind/brain_, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1986, p. 406. [25] Daniel Dennett, "Quining Qualia," in A.J. Marcel & E. Bisiach, eds., _Consciousness and contemporary science_, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988. [26] Thomas Nagel, "What is it like to be a bat?," _Philosophical Review_ 83:4 (1974). [27] William G. Lycan, "What is the 'subjectivity' of the mental?", in James Tomberlin, ed., _Philosophical Perspectives vol. 4: Action theory and the philosophy of mind_, Atascadero: Ridgeview Publishing, 1990, p. 126. [28] Patricia S. Churchland, "Reduction and the neurobiological basis of consciousness," in Marcel & Bisiach, eds., _Consciousness and contemporary science_, p. 282. [29] Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, _New Essays on Human Understanding_, P. Remnant & J. Bennett, ed. & trans. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982, book II, chapter I, sect. 15. [30] Rene Descartes, Oeuvres, C. Adam & P. Tannery, eds. 11 vols., reprint, Paris: Vrin, 1964-1974, vol. IX, p. 60. [31] Paul M. Churchland, _The Engine of reason, the seat of the soul_, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995, p. 198. [32] David Armstrong, in his exchange with Norman Malcolm, _Consciousness and causality. A debate on the nature of mind_, Oxford: Blackwell, 1984, p. 112. See Armstrong's _A Materialist theory of the mind_, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1968 (2nd ed., 1993), pp. 100-115, for the materialist's reconstruction of introspection. [33] Lycan, "What is the 'subjectivity' of the
mental?", [34] See e.g. J.J.C. Smart, "The Identity theory
of mind," _Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy_ (http://plato.stanford.edu)
(2000) and Armstrong, in Armstrong & Malcolm, _Consciousness and
causality_, pp. [35] Charles Olson, "Proprioception" [1961-1962], in _Collected Prose_, ed. Donald Allen & Benjamin Friedlander, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1997, pp. 181, 182. Thanks to Homa Shojaie for helping me locate this text. [36] See Walter J. Freeman, "The Physiology of Perception," _Scientific American_ 264 (February 1991) and _How Brains Make Up Their Minds_, London: Weidenfeld & Nicholson, 1999. [37] Lycan, "What is the 'subjectivity' of the mental?", p. 117. [38] Erwin Straus, _Du sens des sens_, Grenoble: J. Millon, 1989, p. 183. [39] Deleuze & Guattari, _Qu'est-ce que la philosophie?_, pp. 197-198. [40] For Merleau-Ponty's overtly mystical statements about 'Flesh' see e.g. _Phenomenology of perception_, trans. Colin Smith, London: Routledge Kegan Paul, 1962, p. 212: "Just as the sacrament not only symbolizes... an operation of Grace, but is also the real presence of God... in the same way the sensible has not only a motor and vital significance but is a way of being in the world... sensation is literally a form of communion." [41] On the social brain, see Paolo Virno, "Multitude
et principe d'individuation," _Multitudes_ 7 (December 2001), [42] Andy Clark, _Natural-Born Cyborgs_, pp. 11, 43.
Clark intersects here with a good deal of recent cultural theory, media
theory, and literary theory (when it concerns itself with the relation
between fiction, embodiment and technological forms) -- see in particular
Donna Haraway's "cyborgs" (in "A Cyborg Manifesto: Science, [43] Clark, _Being There_, p. 45. [44] Ibid., pp. 21, 87. [45] V.S. Ramachandran & L. Levi et al., "Illusions of body image," p. 34. [46] Clark, _Natural-Born Cyborgs_, p. 86. [47] Hayles, "Flesh and Metal: Reconfiguring the Mindbody in Virtual Environments," p. 300. [48] Gilles Deleuze, _Negotiations 1972-1990_, trans. M. Joughin, New York: Columbia University Press, 1995, p. 26. [49] Contrast Steven Quartz & Terry Sejnowski's
"neural constructivism" (essentially a kind of 'hyper-plasticity')
with Gazzaniga's insistence that we actually have less plasticity than
is currently thought. Further, consider the 'new innatist' point that
phantom limbs imply the existence of internal representations of our
body which we are born with (e.g., the fetus which knows how to put
its thumb in its mouth without 'putting out its eye', an example [50] On the theme of the "cultured brain"
see Warren Neidich, _Blow-Up. Photography, cinema and the brain_, New
York: Distributed Art Publishers, 2003. A 'Deleuzean approach' to the
brain is a significant component of Neidich's analysis; for a helpful
discussion of Deleuze on the brain see John Rajchman, _The Deleuze Connections_, [51] Antonio Negri, "Alma Venus. Prolegomena to the common," trans. Patricia Dailey & Constantino Costantini, in Charles T. Wolfe, ed., _The Renewal of Materialism_ (Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 22:1, New York, New School for Social Research, 2000), 16b. Online at http://www.generation-online.org/t/almavenus.htm [52] Ibid. [53] See http://www.stelarc.va.com.au and http://www.orlan.net [54] As suggested by an anonymous reviewer for CTheory.net [55] Michael Hardt & Antonio Negri, _Empire_, Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000, p. 362. For more on Negri's notion
of "constitutive ontology," see my discussion, "Materialism
and temporality. On Antonio Negri's 'constitutive' ontology," in
Timothy S. Murphy & Abdul-Karim Mustapha, eds., _The Philosophy
of Antonio -------------------- |