|
LONG A mainstay
of contemporary European poststructuralism, the work of Michel Serres
has as yet failed to find an audience amongst British and North American
social scientists. This despite the appearance of his name in the opening
dedication to Bruno Latours The Pasteurization of France, its
recurrence throughout the footnotes and supporting text of Deleuze and
Guattaris seminal A Thousand Plateaus (1988), and, moreover, his
founding influence upon Actor-Network Theory (Callon, 1980;
Latour, 1993; Law, 1997). This lamentable situation is compounded by
the fact that the two dozen or so books which make up his oeuvre (only
half of which have as yet been translated into English) deal in a sustained
fashion with one of the most pressing contemporary issues namely
the reformulating of the once great and now weatherworn Enlightenment
divisions between self and collective, society and nature, the scientific
and the literary, myth and politics. In an age where the rhetoric of
interdisciplinarity is commonplace, it still shocks to encounter work
where the deliberate crossing (and re-crossing) of disciplinary boundaries
is seriously put into
practice. A typical Serres text will, for example, move from information
theory to myth by way of examples drawn from literature or art. Or else
bring the ancient and the modern world into juxtaposition through detailed
exegesis of Lucretius or Liebniz. In Serres work philosophy is
made to inhabit hard science as myth is brought to life within social
science. Jules Verne intermingles with Plato and Thales. Don Juan and
La Fontaine rub shoulders with Descartes.
This may at first sound like the very worst kind of postmodern carnival,
yet Serres border crossings are always rigorously structured.
He proceeds from the notion that disciplinary and conceptual divisions,
although complex
and provisional, may be analysed by exploring potential channels or
passages that run between them. Communication runs through
these passages, but does so only at the risk of potential distortion,
in the course of which messages become transformed. Serres understands
this transformation as both a necessary risk which must be taken to
communicate at all and, more importantly, as a possible source of invention.
He dubs the particular division between science and the humanities as
the Northwest Passage, referring to the twisting and convoluted
coastlines that separate the great Atlantic and Pacific Oceans. Serres
point is that such a divide is there to be traversed it is an
adventure to be had (Serres with Latour, 1995: 70) but
this requires undertaking the most testing of journeys, one that will
involve much doubling back and complex navigation.
One also requires a range of tools. In his early work, notably the Hermes
series of books, Serres draws on mathematics and information theory,
often liberally, to model the variety of interdisciplinary problems
he addresses. His essay on The Origin of Language (in Serres,
1982a), for example, uses a model of the progressive filtering of signals
from noise by way of a chain of conversions (or rectifications)
to explicate not only Freudian repression, but also as a means of understanding
Freuds relationship
to 19th-century science. Now it is the apparently freewheeling fashion
in which Serres generalizes models which has attracted the greatest
critical ire (Hayles, 1989, 1990; Sokal and Bricmont, 1997). Such criticisms
are, however, often based on a profound misinterpretation of what Serres
is actually seeking to achieve. As he puts it in a discussion with Bruno
Latour, the utility of the models he draws upon is that they enable
a way of conceiving provisional connections between otherwise disparate
phenomena:
[M]athematics
teaches rapid thought. Whoever writes x can mean simultaneously
1, 2, 3, the infinite, rationals and transcendents, real and complex
numbers, even quaternions this is an economy of thought. When
you reproach me with Structure isnt enough; youve
got to add all the intermediate steps, this is not a mathematical
thought. Philosophers love intermediate inferences; mathematicians gladly
dispense with them. An elegant demonstration skips the intermediate
steps. Indeed, there is a slowness particular to philosophers that often
strikes me as affection and a speed to
mathematical thought that plays with amazing shortcuts. (Serres with
Latour, 1995: 68)
Here Serres indicates
an important aspect of his methodological approach an approach
that he broadly characterizes as structural.
Continua
>>>>>
|